1. "CAPURRO'S TRILEMMA"
WH:
Dear
Rafael, in order to start our dialogue, I would appreciate your giving
the first contribution by answering the following question: what
conclusions
do you draw from the logical trilemma in your speech at the
conference?
RC:
Dear Wolfgang, may I first summarize the content of the logical
trilemma,
or "Capurro's trilemma" as you called it in your paper "Informatio
revisited" (1).
Information
may mean the same at all levels (univocity), or something similar
(analogy),
or something different (equivocity). In the first case we lose all
qualitative
differences, as for instance when we say that e-mail and cell
reproduction
are the same kind of information process. Not only the "stuff" and the
structure but also the processes in cells and computer devices are
rather
different from each other. If we say the concept of information is
being
used analogically, then we have to state what the "original" meaning
is.
If it is the concept of information at the human level, then we are
confronted
with anthropomorphisms if we use it at a non-human level. We would say
that "in some way" atoms "talk" to each other, etc. Finally there is
equivocity,
which means that information in physics and information in education
are
wholly different concepts. In this case, information cannot be a
unifying
concept any more, i.e. it cannot be the basis for the new paradigm you
are looking for.
Your
conclusion or "solution" of this trilemma is: we go back to the
etymological
roots (information as "giving form") and we take an evolutionary
perspective
where qualities can emerge. I call this solution "dialectical
informatism"
(DIAINF), considering it to be a new version of dialectical materialism
(DIAMAT).
I
think
there are several questions to be considered, which I have listed
below.
1.
The Kantian quest for the limits of human reason.
2.
The metaphysical quest for a unifying principle (like energy, matter,
spirit,
subjectivity, substance, or information) of reality.
3.
Wittgenstein's quest for "language games" which are different from each
other but nonetheless have a family-type relationship.
4.
Gregory Bateson's definition of information as "any difference that
makes
a difference", this being different from information in the sense of
the
mental processes of "finding a difference" (information as meaning) (2).
5.
Luhmann's distinction between information and communication or between
social and psychic systems. Information is a category of solely psychic
systems, it is a system-internal property that is not transferred,
whereas
communication means to open, on the basis of information (or meaning) a
horizon of choices for other persons. Pure communication and pure
information
are at opposite ends of the spectrum (3).
6.
The question of scientific language as a question of separating (or
liberating)
thinking from (everyday) language.
7.
The possibility of a "blind spot" in any unified theory.
8.
The "practical" question of the relationship between information and
money;
information as something we have to pay for.
9.
The quest for a networked structure of different information concepts
as
an alternative to a dialectical view.
10.
The quest for the relationship between information and imagination.
But
now to your question about my conclusions from the logical trilemma in
my speech at the conference. I draw one basic conclusion, namely the
task
of remembering the trilemma when considering the possibility of a
unified
theory of information; in other words, the task of remembering the
differences
between the differences that make a difference. This was in some way a
plea for analogy and even equivocity. I believe that we can take a
reductive
view of reality under the viewpoint of, for instance, an
information-processing
concept. We would then say: whatever exists can be digitalized. Being
is computation. Such a reductive view is useful in many respects
but
we have to pay a high price for it, because we have to leave aside
other
basic phenomena which belong to different levels of reality. This is
the
problem faced by dialectical informatism, as I call it. Dialectical
informatism,
I believe, has an over-optimistic view of the capacity of human
reasoning.
This is why I pointed to Kant in my speech.
Is
there any possibility of a unified theory of information which includes
"Capurro's trilemma" as a constituent element of it, and not as
something
to be eliminated or "solved"? Well, this is a difficult question. Maybe
we should take a look at the metaphysics of Leibniz. Leibniz considers
reality to have two aspects, namely "monads" and matter. There are no
monads
without matter (except God),and vice-versa. Monads and matter are
folded
into the different levels of reality in an infinitely complicated way. This
means that it is not possible for us to have a "true"
view of all
the "steps" faced by unfolding (or "evolution"). This means,
roughly
speaking, that we are faced with infinite concepts of information,
something
which cannot be overlooked by any kind of theory. But on the other
hand,
when we are using different concepts of information, we can
metaphysically
presuppose that they are equivocal, or that our analogies are not
completely
false, without ever really knowing which is the real or true "primum
analogatum".
In other words, from the point of view of our finite reason, a unified
theory of information has to learn how to "play" with equivocity,
analogy
and univocity, thus keeping the trilemma in mind - as a
chance!
2.
DIALECTICAL INFORMATISM AND CAUSALITY OF INFORMATION
PF:
Dear
Rafael, in a somewhat pejorative manner you have described the concept
of information which Wolfgang and I discussed in "Informatio Revisited"
as "dialectical informatism". If I understand you correctly, I think by
this allusion to dialectical materialism you are saying that we persist
in using the structure of DIAMAT, with just one exception, namely that
we have replaced its main object, matter, by information; you seem to
think
that we are leaving everything else unchanged, in particular the
dialectical
way of thinking. I am not convinced that your argument points correctly
to the core of our proposal, i.e. a methodology for perceiving
information.
Although Wolfgang and I share the method of dialectical thinking, we
have
different ideas about the possibility of a unified
information-science.
I
hope
to be able to make my position clear. What I am looking for is not
a
replacement of matter by information (as you seem to assume), but the
pursuit
of a broader and more integrated concept, in which matter and
information
can coexist. Furthermore, I am looking for interconnections and
linkages
between matter and information. Thus, I am seeking notions which may be
general enough to cope with the two alternative ways of describing
reality.
In
my opinion, one basic notion which can be applied generally is the term
"causality". This concept is used in everyday language, in mythological
thinking, and in scientific languages as well. Therefore there a chance
exists to adapt it to our situation, to extend it towards our needs,
and
to explicate it more precisely. I think it constructive to look for
information
from this perspective, and to work out the differences/similarities
between
the causality of information processes and that of physical
processes.
The advantage of this perspective is the unfolding of larger range of
analysis
than is permitted by physics. It allows for the inclusion of completely
different causal relations which cannot be viewed by the natural
sciences.
I
will
try to sketch the main argument: For human beings it is essential to
understand
the world; the reason for understanding it is the need to control it,
the
reason for controlling it is the necessity for survival. According to
Kant,
the principle of causality is the a priori of how we talk about this
possibility
of control (although we have to modify its precise content). Cassirer
taught
us that the content of this principle is not only applicable in
physics,
but in everyday modern (and, as I see it, post modern), and
mythological
thinking as well. Nevertheless the understanding of the principle has
changed
considerably over time. Here we will not deal with the variations of
the
content of causality throughout the history of physics, but prefer to
look
for the difference and the implications of the causal principle between
the physical and informational processes.
So,
on each level of investigation (e.g. in physics or in biology or in
social
sciences) we will try to answer the following question: "How is this
part
of reality handled/controlled by internal or external forces?". The
answer
which is given by physics is evident: it is possible because of the
Causal
Principle which is the basis of laws of nature. One has to control the
cause to bring about any effect. Laws of Conservation in physics (of
energy,
of matter, or of impulse) reduce the "freedom of choice" (i.e.
diversity)
of possible effects. Some kind of automatism is applied. "If I do this,
nature answers like that". Mechanical materialism believes in the
unique
effect of any cause (Laplace's daemon was the metaphor used to
characterize
the omniscient status of a scientist who knew the status of the entire
world at any one moment). Today causality in physics represents a
general,
immediate, and local relation between physically measurable variables
which
are non-symmetrical with respect to cause and effect.
Information,
on the other hand, is able to mediate between cause and effect without
having to obey the Laws of Conservation as such. There is no need for
uniqueness
of the effect. More than that, not even the type or quality of the
effect
needs to be predictable. One of the main differences between physics
and
information sciences can thus be seen here. While physics is oriented
towards
forecasting effects based on some explicated premise, information
sciences
have to deal with the structure of the unpredictable. At first glance
this
seems to be a very fuzzy enterprise, but it is in fact the complement
of
the unique predictability of the physical world. The new cannot be
grasped
theoretically by physics. If everything were uniquely predictable in a
physical environment, no development of the world would be
possible.
A
second
difference can be found between physical and informational processes.
Physical
units (in particular in classical mechanics) are based on the
metaphysical
principle of some factor (like mass, force, energy) while the
substantialism
gets lost in the realm of information. Information in its reified
aspect
is like a symbol, a metaphor. It is more a pointer to some kind of
interpretation
process than an object per se. It does not always point to any object
of
so-called reality. If there is some conscious process needed to
interpret
the pointer, and thus to create a new piece of reality, the
substantiality
of information is no longer needed. By the same argument, uniqueness of
interpretation is no longer assured; on the contrary, in information
processes
there must be freedom of choice, on some level there must even be
unpredictability,
there must be the opportunity for creativity, and producing something
new.
Here Leibniz's monads could come into the picture. They could be
interpreted
as an early concept to explain the half of the world which was left out
by mechanical materialism, such as processes of the human mind, the
soul
and creativity. In my opinion there is no need to stick to Leibniz's
interpretation
of the monads as being divinely created. The concept of information
processes
would allow for a materialistic explanation.
So
far I have tried to show the differences between information and
physical
processes. But there are similarities as well. While the physical
process
in the history of science originates from uniqueness and
predictability,
more and more uncertainty has come up in physics during the last few
decades.
Quantum mechanics has shown that we have two options. The first is to
stick
to the uniqueness of causality as in traditional mechanical
materialism;
this has the disadvantage that one has to restrict the realm of
"reality"
to the world of the systems, not to the elements themselves.
Alternatively,
one could bring randomness into the picture, thus widening the notion
of
causality, weakening the uniqueness of the link between cause and
effect.
I prefer the latter interpretation as a suitable solution to this
dilemma.
However, the distinctiveness of processes of information then
shrinks.
From
another point of view, information processes resemble physical
processes.
It is the lack of a strict Law of Conservation of Energy in Einstein's
general theory of relativity. Another source of indeterminism is the
notion
of mathematical chaos which was found in a huge number of models that
describe
the physical world. Although we could forecast the future and the past
of our world if we knew the state of the world at one single moment,
chaos
theory has taught us that processes exist which depend so heavily on
initial
conditions that small changes in the latter can radically alter the
former.
On
a completely different level, a second example of resemblance can be
given.
As Einstein showed, the Law of Conservation of Energy does not hold for
his General Theory of Relativity.
The
similarity of physical process to information processes can be found as
well. If information, with its syntax, semantics, and pragmatics is
used
in a reified and fixed manner, the information process can play a very
similar role to that of a physical link. All industrial automation
processes
are of this type. The unique and predictable reaction to a certain
situation
is the core feature of any automated assembly line, of a computerized,
numerically controlled machine tool, or a PC. Because of their high
independence
from any laws of conservation, engineers prefer them to physical
feedback
systems (e.g. the centrifugal-force regulator or mechanically
controlled
automated looms).
I
hope
that these statements will destroy your suspicion that our goal would
be
the mere replacement of matter by information, whilst retaining a
dialectical
concept.
3.
CONCEPTIONS OF CAUSALITY
RC:
Dear
Peter, I am glad that the pejorative undertone of my criticism has
become
an incentive for, not an obstacle to, our dialogue. I see, indeed, some
similarities between the interpretation(s) of reality provided by
dialectical
materialism and the view of a general information science with an
evolutionary
perspective. Of course, we cannot fully discuss here the questions of
what
dialectics, materialism or informatism in all their historical and
theoretical
complexity are. With the term "dialectical informatism" I was trying to
put a marker on the discussion. But your are right, "isms" always
indicate
something pejorative in the sense of an exaggeration. My question is
"Where
are the limits of such an information science?" or "Where are the
limits
of the notion of information as a basic concept for understanding
reality?"
You
suggest that the concept of causality should be applied not only to
matter
but also to information, and you mention "the differences/similarities
between the causality of information processes and that of physical
processes".
This proposition is, I think, a clear denial of informatism as such;
everything
is information, or physical processes are to be understood basically in
terms of information, or the like.
You
speak about causality of matter and causality of information. Maybe we
should recapitulate some of the questions connected with the concept of
causality in general. As you know, causality is a concept deeply rooted
in Western philosophy. The so-called Pre-Socratic philosophers used the
concepts of arché and aition in trying to
understand
nature from a non-mythical viewpoint. It was Aristotle who, based on
his
interpretation of the Platonic "forms" as well as what we could call
the
"pottery model" of production or causation established a four-part
distinction
of causality. Since the Middle Ages, these four kinds of causation have
popularly been known as causa materialis, causa formalis,
causa efficiens, and causa finalis.
Arché
and aition were translated into Latin as causa and ratio
and were sometimes used as synonyms, although being the "real" cause of
something is different from the "reason" why something happens.
According
to Leibniz, everything that exists must have a "sufficient reason" for
its coming into being. Therefore, according to metaphysical
argumentation,
there must be a fundamental reason why there is something at all,
rather
than nothing, i.e. something that has its reason for being in itself:
God
as Causa sui as Spinoza called it.
Plato's demiourg in
the
"Timaios", a kind of
"pottery god",
became (under
Christian metaphysics) a transcendent creator as causa efficiens
and finalis of nature, separated from immanent causality. This
can
be seen, for instance, in Thomas Aquina's distinction between creatio
and informatio. Causality per informationem, or
immanent
causality, presupposes that something already exists on (or in) which
the
cause produces an effect, for instance the processes of life or
understanding.
Causality per creationem, or transcendent causality, is God's
prerogative
and means the capability of producing something out of nothing (ex
nihilo).
Metaphysics
also made a distinction between two forms of immanent causality: a
"transitive"
immanent causality, where a cause can change or even disappear in the
process
of (in)formation, and another immanent causality where the cause
remains
the same although changes may take place. The latter is the case for
e.g.
human or animal souls. The transcendent cause must be "higher" than
immanent
causality.
The
idea of a transcendent cause was criticized by modern natural
scientists
who looked only for the immanent empirical laws of nature. This is, I
think,
what you are referring to when you talk about causality of matter,
which
was supposed, at least until the quantum physics debate, deterministic.
Modern causality is conceived not only in terms of the immanent
causality
of the laws of nature but also as an evolutionary or "transitive"
causality.
The question is now whether evolution can be seen as an "information"
process
following rules or laws or, as you suggest, a deterministic causality
of
matter and an indeterministic causality of information must be
distinguished.
I think you are giving, against the modern conception, the primacy to
the
latter.
The
modern philosophical debate on causality was influenced by Empiricism
as
well as by Kant. According to Kant, the concept of cause is on the one
hand something we do not get out of the phenomena, but it is something
that belongs to our understanding of them (contrary to what empiricists
such as Hume believed). On the other hand, the rule of human reason,
i.e.
"every effect has a cause" remains empty until we apply it empirically.
Whether or not reality or nature as a whole and "in themselves" obey
this
rule is something that goes beyond the capacity of our theoretical
knowledge.
Kant
also inherited and transformed the distinction between immanent and
transcendent
causality. His "practical reason" acts according to a "causality of
freedom"
that can be considered from a naturalistic point of view as a
contradictory
concept or at least as an oxymoron, a verbal contradiction. Kant's
solution
of this "contradictio" ("Widerspruch") is his dual view of two separate
levels of reality, freedom and necessity, causality of freedom and
causality
of matter, that are not in (logical) contradiction, but in an
existential
(or ethical) "struggle" ("Widerstreit") with each other, as they belong
to two different ontological dimensions. For Kant, freedom was a fact
that
could not be explained by theoretical reason and natural
causality.
This
is, of course, a very uncomfortable situation for modern natural
science,
which is looking for "solutions" ("Lösung") in terms of
deterministic
causal explanations and not for the Kantian philosophic "dissolution"
("Auflösung")
of his antinomies through causality struggles. Nowadays there is
therefore
the question of whether Kant can be naturalized, for example given an
evolutionary
conception of the "a priori" structures of reason or an emergent
explanation
of human freedom. In such a conception the immanent deterministic
principle causa aequat effectum is being superseded, or at
least
delimited
or complemented, as you say, by a non-symmetrical but immanent
relationship
between cause and effect. Explaining reality means in this case dealing
not only with deterministic material causation but also with
non-deterministic
informational causation.
It
is in this sense, I believe, that you speak of a new kind of causality,
a causality of information. The question is, whether this different
type
of causation gives rise, as you say, to a new distinction between the
sciences
and in what way this distinction could be interpreted, namely as two
complementary
ways of understanding the whole of reality, as a formal or
methodological
distinction, or as a distinction that arises from different phenomena,
a "real" distinction (cum fundamento in re). The latter
alternative
would be a new version of the difference between natural and social
sciences
or between the "Geisteswissenschaften"and the "Naturwissenschaften"
according
to the 19th century German terminology. The first alternative would
imply
some kind of naturalization of the concept of information, considering
all natural processes as open to new and unpredictable "information".
This
is, I think, what Tom Stonier was talking about and what Carl Friedrich
von Weizsäcker is also considering when he connects the concept of
information to its philosophical origins in Plato's and Aristotle's
forms.
This
would fit with your interpretation of Leibniz's dualism of matter and
monads,
which can also be interpreted as a monism as far as matter is an
"expression"
of the monads or, what comes nearer to your view, as an original
twofold
"pre-established harmony", not of two substances, but of two dimensions
unfolding themselves through infinite possibilities. Your examples from
relativity and chaos theory show that we are becoming aware of
indeterministic
processes in nature and this leads to the present challenge of the
primacy
of deterministic causation of matter.
This
makes possible your turning over (if I might call it that) the modern
view
that tries to explain all processes under the deterministic premises of
the causality of matter. Within the deterministic view, time is a
homogeneous
succession of instants. Our causal explanations are supposed to be in
the
order of the before (cause) and the after (effect). Time in itself,
being
a homogeneous frame, is reversible. You point to this by saying that
according
to determinism, we could forecast the future (and describe the past) of
our world if we knew the state of the world at one single moment
(Laplace's
daemon).
In
contrast, the causality of information allows only a prediction in a
non-homogeneous
time. Past, present and future are not reversible. This does not just
mean
that we can make any kind of "predictions" or that "anything can
happen",
but that informational explanations are probabilistic and no "daemon"
can
give us a firm knowledge about future effects.
My
question is now whether on the basis of your distinction we are dealing
with a) a difference between physics and information sciences (you are
using the plural!), or b) with physics (and chemistry and biology
and...)
as information sciences, with different (infinite?) information
concepts.
Is the principle of causal information "just" a formal
("transcendental")
frame for the study of different effects under the premises of their
informational
causes? In what sense can we say that informational causes have at
least
partly unpredictable effects ("causa informationis non aequat
effectum")?
In what sense does this principle of non-equality gives rise to the
information
trilemma? I mean, in what sense does that which is considered to be an
information process (for instance at the biological level) give rise to
the non-equivalent emergence of consciousness, whose information
processes,
being non-equivalent with the ones that caused it, are now the cause of
societal ones etc.?
It
seems to me that as in the case of matter, the concept of information
changes
(analogically? equivocally?) in the different levels (and what remains
is "only" a void or formal causality of information). When we study
matter
in physics, biology, and the social sciences, the meaning of this
concept
changes dramatically. The concept of matter is a "polymorphic" one. We
have no "science(s) of matter", the "matter" of physics is far away
(how
far?) from the "matter" of, say, literature. What (natural) sciences
have
had in common with each other is (until now) the causality of matter as
a formal principle. Dialectical materialism gives, I think, a primacy
to
the causality of matter. But here again we are facing the trilemma!
This
was the reason for my "warning" about "dialectical informatism"; as far
as it remains deterministic, it gives the primacy to a specific level
of
reality, and it is supposed to say something about reality in itself"
or
as a whole (mixing, in Kantian terms, the "ontological" with the
"transcendental").
It seems to me that instead of extending the causality of matter (and
determinsm)
to a "non-material" dimension of reality (history, literature etc.), we
are now trying to do the contrary, taking the causality of information
as a basis .
But
if, according to Kant, in the case of causation of information we
cannot
say either that all reality is "informed" or capable of being
"informed"
(God being, metaphysically speaking, the forma formarum), and,
more
basically, if the concept of causality (being a "transcendental"
concept)
is one way of interpreting nature (in an objective deterministic and/or
indeterministic way), then we have to ask ourselves whether the model
of
nature that gave rise to such a concept is the only legitimate one.
This
is the point stated by Heidegger when he analyzes the experience of
"nature"
(physis) in Pre-Socratic philosophy.
According
to Heidegger, "physis" was primarily seen as a process of
"unconcealment",
where something emerges, becoming "un-concealed", whereas at the
same time there remains a basic dimension of "concealment", which can
not
be adequately grasped in terms of causation, and particularly of
production.
The process of "producing" (or of "bringing something forth") has an
affinity
to the imagery of pottery. What metaphysics does is, roughly speaking,
project the pottery model back into the experience of nature as
"unconcealment".
The concept of causality being, according to Heidegger, a metaphysical
concept, "forgets" or takes for granted the twofold dimension of the
given
of nature, or tries to explain the given-ness of the given with the
help
of a transcendent cause. According to a non-metaphysical experience,
nature
has no ground, and this "having no ground" is shown (and concealed) as
"unconcealment". Gratuity, the given-ness of the given, is more basic
than
causation. This is something, I think, that goes beyond the question of
determinism or indeterminism, and therefore beyond the primacy of the
causality
of information with regard to causality of matter. But at the same
time,
your concept of causality of information seems to question the imagery
of pottery as well as the idea that the whole of reality is a kind of
hardware
and software pool, where all kinds of "information" can be produced,
stored,
manipulated etc., although this is, I think, an almost obvious
interpretation
of the causality of information within the metaphysical background of
today's
information processing systems. Nature would then be considered to be a
gigantic information network instead of a gigantic clockwork
mechanism.
4.
THE UNITY OF THE UNIVERSE AND THE UNITY OF SCIENCE
WH:
Dear
Peter, may I enter the discussion here, please? We are talking about a
distinction we draw in causality, namely between causality of
informational
processes and causality of material processes, of matter – as
you put
it,
Rafael –,
that is causality without informational
aspects.
Before
I deal with your question, Rafael, (as to whether this means a
distinction
in science as well), let me point out that I do not think that this
distinction
is a question of being either a formal, methodological distinction or a
material, real one. In my view these two aspects are not independent of
one another. We use the method of drawing the distinction because we
suppose
that there is such a difference between the two kinds of causation in
reality.
But,
having said this – and
here I come to the crucial point –,
this by no
way
entails the prolongation of the divide between natural sciences and
social
sciences. You know, Rafael, that I am a strong advocate of the unity of
all science. Differences in what different disciplines are
investigating
do not automatically imply that they are obliged to use different
methods
exclusively. There are common features as well, mutual facets lying in
the objects to the same extent to which the objects differ from each
other.
We have good reasons to assume that the universe, though constituted of
a probably infinite number of different parts, does not fall apart. The
universe is one and many fold at the same time.
So,
the distinction between several kinds of causation is not primarily a
structural
distinction between disciplines in the system of sciences. It's rather
a historical distinction - a distinction between an old-fashioned world
view in which all processes are deterministic and in which there is no
room for indeterminism, on the one hand, and an emerging new world view
which allows for conceiving deterministic processes as a special case
of
the intrinsic non-deterministic character of the unfolding universe on
the other. We are facing a paradigm shift so fundamental that it
entangles
not only science but also our everyday views. And what is very
important:
it does not do away with the former findings but includes them in
setting
limits to them. That is: under certain circumstances we find
deterministic
causation, but this is not the usual case.
The
emerging information science is part of this paradigm shift. It is not
all of the new paradigm itself. The new paradigm says: we live in a
self-organizing universe in which the future is open, though there are
certain constraints. As to me, information science says: information
comes
into play where self-organization takes place. Here I want to draw
your attention, Rafael, to another point. There is no sharp difference
between matter and information. The latter arises from the former. That
is, if matter transcends the limits of determination, if it begins to
organize
itself, then information is generated. The philosophical background of
this is emergentism. Emergentist philosophy, as developed for instance
by Lewis Morgan and summed up by David Blitz in a recent book on
Emergent
Evolution, holds that effects which do not "result" from causes, that
is,
which are not "resultant" but "emergent", cannot be "reduced" to their
causes. In this case causa non aequat effectum, causation is only a
necessary
constraint, but not a sufficient one as it is in mechanistic causation.
Thus, standing on the base of the concept of emergence, you have on the
one hand the opportunity to stick to the concept of causality, which
means
that there is nothing which was created out of nothing (let's leave the
question of the coming into being of the universe out), and on the
other
hand there remains enough openness to let novelties arise which did not
exist before. So there is also a continuum between matter (which is
self-organizing)
and information (which is bound to self-organization and therefore
bound
to matter as a necessary precondition), though there is a discontinuity
between the two.
In
other words, I want to stress that there are no absolute differences.
Thinking
distinction and oneness in one –
something like that is maybe
dialectical
thinking. Stating that there are only distinctions to be drawn and no
common
ground to be detected belongs to the positivistic way of thinking which
is overcome nowadays by the paradigm shift towards taking the whole
into
account. But –
what
counts even more – it
would be a sad and dull world
in which we had to live, if the concept of equivocity were right. This
would indeed be like the work on the tower of Bable. Aren't human lives
self-organizing systems which construct their paths decision by
decision?
And is it unthinkable to drop a view which sets formal logic
absolutely,
and to adopt another one which better fits the flexible developments
around
us?
What
I want to state is that your trilemma, Rafael, is also due to a very
special
view of the world. If, instead, I postulate an emergentist view, a view
of evolutionary systems which organize themselves, I can avoid
extending
one level of reality to another as well – there is no need to have a
primum
analogatum, because the systems are not thought to be analogous, but
related
to each other, depending on each other, arising from each other, and
therefore
establishing common features and different features. If I postulate
this
view, I can think the general and the specific together, and then there
is no dilemma whatsoever anymore.
I
admit
that there is no possibility of gaining absolute knowledge of what is
going
on in the universe (including ourselves). But you have already admitted
– if
I didn't misunderstand you –
that we obviously continually succeed
in gaining relative knowledge and even better, comprising knowledge. We
have to be pluralistic just in order not to overlook a possibility of
attaining
another piece of knowledge and to go one step further. In this sense, a
unified theory of information cannot be designed as a closed dogma. But
we may take into account that every time we in the scientific community
reach an agreement on some hypothesis, we are producing some bricks for
the build-up of the theory.
5.
MATTER AND INFORMATION
PF:
Dear
Wolfgang, dear Rafael, just a few comments on Wolfgang's last excursion
into matter and information. I think I can agree with most of your
arguments.
There is only one paragraph that I find somewhat misleading. It is
linked
to the relationship between matter and information.
Wolfgang,
you wrote: "there is also a continuum between matter (which is
self-organizing)
and information (which is bound to self-organization and therefore
bound
to matter as a necessary precondition), though there is a discontinuity
between the two."
Although
I agree with you, Wolfgang, on your statement that matter is a
precondition
of information, I wonder whether the term "continuum" is an appropriate
characteristic for the relationship between matter and information. In
my opinion these two belong to different ontological categories.
Wolfgang,
you describe the relationship as if there were a development of matter
towards information. But the notion of development means a qualitative
and quantitative change of some entity which stays the same over time.
While matter in physicists' terms is inseparably linked to energy and
mass
(both properties of matter are conserved, except the general theory of
relativity), information is a different concept.
I
could
agree with you if you stated that information is, or may be, an aspect
of matter or a property of it, but it would be misleading to say that
information
is nothing but transformed matter. In my opinion, information has a
special
symbolic aspect; we want to stress that its materiality is not the
essence
of it, although of course reified information cannot be exchanged
without
a materially mediated process. Under the material aspect of information
there have to be some structures, be they transient or invariable over
long periods of time. But these structures do not refer to themselves,
but to other phenomena (this is the semantic level). In my opinion the
basic difference from physical relationships is the principle of
exchangeability
in the process of information creation. It is not fixed by the symbol
which
represents some sequence of actions or some physical objects or
subjects.
And in the more recent developments of evolution, in particular in
human
beings, the constructivist feature of information is of particular
importance.
New views may come up, and may change essentially the behavior of the
interacting
partners (pragmatic level).
I
would
summarize my argument as follows: information emerges at a certain
state
of development of matter, but is not matter itself. It has some
material
aspect, but this is not essential. It needs a symbolic representation,
referring to other objects, processes or thoughts. Symbolic
representation
implies that there is no unique determination of the symbol. Symbols
could
be taken from existing objects, but they could be invented and created
anew as well. Sometimes implicitly or explicitly construction
processes,
bargaining processes and power are involved in the information
process.
WH:
Dear Peter, let me give just a short answer. My intention was to argue
against dualism. There are no two substances like matter and
information
which are absolutely independent of each other. The laws of physics are
valid and hold for all phenomena insofar as they have physical aspects.
Insofar as they have emergent properties which go beyond physical
properties,
laws of physics do not tell us very much. They give only constraints,
but
do not determine the specific nature of the new quality of the
phenomenon
in question. We have material systems which do not show informational
qualities,
and we have material systems which show informational qualities. But in
my opinion, there is no information generating/processing system which
does not have a material basis.
6.
HOW NATURE PRODUCES THINGS
RC:
Dear
Wolfgang, I think we are now discussing the content of my first remark
(under Nr. 4) concerning the difference, as Lars Qvortrup puts it,
between
Bateson's definition of information as "any difference that makes a
difference"
and information in the sense of the mental processes of "finding a
difference",
the latter being the concept proposed by constructivists such as Heinz
von Foerster and, according to Qvortrup, by Niklas Luhmann. However,
Luhmann
does not attribute meaning to all biological systems, but only to
psychic
and social ones.
You
say, "There is no sharp difference between matter and information. The
latter arises from the former", and you explain "arises" by saying "if
matter transcends the limits of determination". How is this possible?
How
can indetermination "arise" from determination? And does this mean that
you speak of information only at the level of self-organizing, i.e.
living
beings? Otherwise you would have to consider the difference between
self-organizing
non-living matter and self-organizing living matter. What can this
difference
mean? If you say that the universe (whatever you imagine this concept
to
be!) is per se non-deterministic, then it is not necessary to
say
that information "arises" from matter. We (!) always have to deal with
informed matter.
This
question was discussed by Plato in the "Timaios", as well as in the
"Sophistes".
May I recommend the book by Serge Margel: "Le tombeau du dieu
artisan"
(Paris 1995), whose interpretation of Plato I will now briefly
recapitulate.
The demiourg, the pottery god, "convinces" matter and its
concomitant
necessity to orient towards the ideal form; or, as Plato puts it,
"intelligence
dominates necessity" (Tim. 48a). The world begins with a
"mélange"
of mechanical determination and intelligent order. It remains oriented
towards perfection, but it will never reach it. But what happened, asks
Margel, at and after the beginning? There must be something "there" (!)
which makes possible the relationship between the material or sensible
and the intelligible. This "third genus" is called chora by
Plato.
It is invisible, without form (amorphon) and indestructible
(Tim.
52b). You say, "Let's leave the question of the coming into being of
the
universe out". I think this poses more conceptual difficulties than if
we try to get a coherent view, where even the most difficult elements
are
not left out, but are included as questions (!) in the intelligence
search
process. This is of course a philosophical attitude, but it may also be
useful, in the long run, for scientific hypotheses.
Chora
means something capable of reception, in as much as it is capable of
nutrition
and protection. Plato thus compares it with a "mother" (Tim. 51a). Chora
is something prior to matter, and to information. According to Margel,
the
protective function of chora is neither that of causality, nor
of
a primordial substance, but it is a "representative" one, i.e. it (or
"she"!)
protects the genesis of material things with an orientation (otherwise
they would disappear). The concept of "impression" (typos) used
by Plato in this context was translated into Latin with informatio.
Chora is what makes configurations (or in-formations)
possible.
Plato also compares it with a "riddle" (which is a kind of network)
(Tim.
52d-53b). Chora is the difference that entails all differences
or
forms with their potentialities; otherwise the "demiourg" would not
have
been able to mix them according to their proper structure, being
confronted
by elements with total instability. Before I break off this Platonic
discourse
for a moment I would like to quote a sentence from the "Sophist" (in a
rough translation):
"The
Guest: We are of the opinion that all these [living and non- living
beings
on earth, RC] were generated successively from a former non-being by
the
effect of a god (theou demiourgountos)? Or shall we hang on to
the
common opinion as well as the general gossip?
Theaitetos:
What do you mean?
The
Guest: (...) that nature (physin) produces all these things with
blind causes (apo tinos aitias automates) generating without
intelligence
(dianoias); or is there reason (meta logou) and divine
knowledge
(epistemes theias) from a god producing
them?
Theaitetos:
I really fluctuate again and again between these two possibilities,
maybe
because of my youth." (Soph. 265c-d)
The
reason
why I have brought Plato into our discussion is that we should be
careful
when we speak about paradigm shifts. "New" and "old" are very relative!
But I agree with you that the deterministic paradigm has proved
untenable
and that the "old" idea , as Plato says, of "blind causes" (or, as we
can
literally translate, of "automatic" or self-organizing causes) is now
"the
common opinion".
I
would
like to be a little provocative now. What if the universe is more like
a Tower of Babel than, if you remember Popper's metaphor, a cathedral?
(4)
You say "there is a discontinuity" and that the systems have "common
features
and different features". Well, this is the definition of analogy!
According
to the "new" paradigm we should take the word "difference" seriously,
because
we cannot reduce reactio to actio. Equivocity means
that
we are using the same words for different things. We do this for
instance
as a joke, or when we are looking for a rhetorical effect. My question
is: are we talking equivocally when we say that cells exchange
information
and that human beings exchange information? Why should the universe be
incoherent, given that it is pluralistic, i.e. where different
phenomena
arise that cannot be reduced deterministically to former causes?
Indeed,
as you say, "there are no absolute differences". Why? Because if
something
were absolutely different from anything we may know, then it would be
impossible
for us to understand it!
This
was the problem posed to Christian theologians for whom God was
supposed
to transcend all mundane reality. One way to talk about him without
falling
into the traps of analogy was the "negative theology" (theologia
negativa).
We find a kind of philosophia negativa in Kant's negation of a
reasonable
talk about "things in themselves", and also in present constructivist
theories.
I think it is Konrad Lorenz (and Karl Popper) who uses the word
"fulguration"
when he talks about the (highly) improbable evolution from non-living
matter
to life, and from life to consciousness. There is, I believe, no continuum
between these "fulgurations". We can understand animals only ex
negativo
i.e. in as much as they are not like us. And we do not know what death
(and being born) means. The continuum-hypothesis belongs to what you
call
the "old" deterministic paradigm. The consequence of the idea of
causality
"per informationem" is natura facit saltum. We could also say
that
nature is not completely transparent. According to Heraclit, "nature
likes
to conceal itself" ("physis kryptesthai philei"). We cannot
plainly
(deterministically) explain (and foresee) how differences "arise", but
not know about other possible "fulgurations" in the
universe.
Does
this mean we live in a "paranoic" situation? I do not think this is
necessarily
the case, at least as far as we are able to find differences and to
understand
them as such. We are, in the second sense of the word,
informational
beings, and not only beings with differences that "make" differences.
Non-rational animals do not inform each other, i.e. they cannot grasp,
as far as we know, something "as" something, seeing it in its proper
context.
This is only possible through language. This human prerogative is, of
course,
not a licence for species chauvinism! In this sense, we are the "primum
analogatum" of the information concept and we therefore have to be
careful
about the limits of analogies. The irreducibility of "fulgurations"
opens
the chiasm of equivocity. Of course, there is the question of whether
we
"see" the chiasm of qualitative differences, or whether it is just a
product
of a paranoid imagination. The only way out of this dilemma is again
through
a common delimitation, i.e. through the patient work of mutual
information.
Our logos is conditioned and biased by the process of having to
tell each other what we believe is the case. Human "dia-log" is an
informational
process, entailing the possibility of finding differences together, as
well as of giving a (partially) different sense to the fulgurations,
beginning
with the primordial fulguration of being itself. As we are not the
primordial
origin (and end) of being(s), our "demiourgical logos", or our
world
picture, is not only a delimited but also a biased one. Future
generations
will be able not only to question it with regard to its correctness,
but
also to design new drafts or perspectives (from what has until then
been
concealed), thus giving the possibility of new kinds of relationship
between
man and world. This is the idea of truth as "un-concealment" (in
contrast
to truth as adaequation or correctness) suggested by Heidegger, going
back
to Greek a-letheia.
According
to Peter, information "needs a symbolic representation". This is very
similar
to what Plato says when he talks about chora as a medium for
the
protection of the representations. According to Margel, chora
is
shapeless, but entails "figures" (schemata), i.e. the
specifications
of the transformations of the elements. There are still some very
specific
(and difficult) distinctions in Plato's theory, such as the original
representations
(mimemata) leaving an impression, or typos (the forma
impressa) representing a form (apotupoma or imago
expressa
or the ideal content), and finally the morphai or the defined
schemes.
The schemata build a kind of relatioship between the sensitive
and
the intelligible world. In this context I would like to remember that
for
Kant in his "Kritik der reinen Vernunft", the schemata play a
key
(and obscure) role connecting the categories with the sensitive
data.
My
question now concerns the differences, and similarities, between the
process
of the "in-formation" of matter and the meaning of this process to the demiourg....
and to today's information scientists! I
think we can
agree with Plato in as much as the intelligent activity of the
"demiourg",
his informational activity, is different from the informational process
that took place before his intervention, where the world was "without
proportion
and measure" ("alogos kai ametros") (Tim. 53a). In other words,
if we are now dealing with an organized universe, it is because the
informational
activity of the "demiourg" exists, which was based on a pre-given
symbolic
draft. It is interesting to consider that for Plato, the human soul
undertakes
the task of the demiourg, namely to "save" the world or to give
it a reason (logon didonai), to be responsible for it. We have
to
learn to distinguish both informational processes (before and after the
intervention of the demiourg). In my study on the etymological
roots
of the information concept, I defined information as the determination
of form (genitivus subjectivus and objectivus) (5).
Yes,
"the latter arises from the first", but not in the sense that it could
be reduced to the first or explained by it, but in the sense that the
first
makes responsible informational action possible. According to this
view,
the field of information science is the field of responsible
intelligent
action in order to "save" the world. It is a complementary, and
qualitatively
different action to the one performed by the forms. We are dealing with
a field of open possibilities, and no pre-formation tells us what we
have
to do in order to do the right things. But at the same time, we live in
an age when the gods, and with them their rational "logos", are gone.
The
"demiourg" has lured us, according to Margel's interpretation, with the
impossible promise of transforming the real world into the ideal
one.
For
Plato, the world has thus become "the tomb of the pottery god"
(Margel's
title: "le tombeau du dieu artisan"), in the same way as our bodies are
the tomb of the soul (we are born in a woman's body) which loses the
connection
to the gods and the ideal numbers. At the same time, as the soul takes
the place of the demiourg, it must take care of the connections
between the world and the logos, being capable, as a finite
being,
of failing the logos and ending in "myth" and dissolution. Our
informational
activity would basically be one of learning to die, Socrates'
definition
of philosophical activity. That means learning to understand that the
stories
we tell each other about ourselves and our world are supposed to be logos,
but that they are constantly in danger of becoming a myth, especially
when
we believe the world (in one of its "in-formations") is the fulfilment
of the ideal, instead of keeping the dimension of announcement of an
unattainable
expectation. I would like to link Margel's concept of "expectation"
("attente")
with the non-Platonic mythical concept of announcement (angelia)
that plays a key role in Greek tragedy. Maybe we should define
ourselves
not as "logical" (and mortal) beings (zoon logon echon, animal
rationale et mortale), but as "angelical" or informational ones. Angelia
is, as far as we are concerned, more basic than logos.
Information
is the dimension that enables logos and "myth" to be
communicated.
Dealing with these two ends, it contains something from both, and can
fail
on either side. The information age is our age; this is why we are
looking
for an information science. But we would fail ourselves, and would
bring
the world into dissolution, if we understood ourselves as a fulfilment
of the expectation. Learning to die is our way of opening up to the logos
and to its fragile transmission.
Excuse
me for this long mytho-logical discourse!
7.
ACTIO NON EST REACTIO
WH:
Dear
Rafael, I agree with you that it is very hard to imagine how
indeterministic
relations could have arisen from deterministic ones. Therefore it is
more
convenient to imagine a universe which has been indeterministic (or
more
precisely, not strictly deterministic) from the very beginning. I
prefer
to view the evolution of the cosmos - the universe - as a sequence of
stages
which differ from each other in that later stages show qualities which
did not exist in earlier stages. It's like an unfolding of perpetually
new qualities, a self-organizing universe in which the
self-organization
itself is developing from one kind of self-organization to another kind
of self-organization. Ebeling and his colleagues differentiate a dozen
phases in the development of the cosmos since the Big Bang. And these
phases
are seen by numerous scientists as interlinked via symmetry-breaking
phase
transitions.
Surely
there are non-living material things which are capable of organizing
themselves?
Think of the famous Bénard cells and other dissipative
structures.
And it is precisely because in self-organization processes the
result
does not equal the starting point, and 'reactio' is unequal to 'actio' (for
there is novelty emerging), that I feel a deep
connection between
self-organization and information. And I would like to interpret the
saying
'information is a difference that makes a difference' in the following
way. In self-organizing processes there appears to be a difference
between
the input and the output of a system; this difference is due to a
difference
between some inputs to the system; so to say, the difference in the
environment
is taken by the system to be something which makes a difference to the
system. And this difference which is offered by the system can be taken
by other systems in the environment to be something which makes a
difference
to them, and so on.
Let
me state this clearly. I do not believe that what emerges at a certain
time was pre-existent somewhere else before that time. It could not
have
existed except as potential. So, at the beginning of the universe, the
potential for life, humans and consciousness must have been there as a
disposition, as a chance which could be realized by actual development
(or not). I myself do not believe in anything like god. That's a
personal
conviction, and I respect other convictions. But I see in emergentist
philosophy
a proper tool for tackling such problems, like such as how a new thing
comes into being; matter itself does it, all material systems do it,
when
far away from thermodynamical equilibrium conditions, by having the
ability
to organizing themselves.
I
agree
with you fully when you describe emergence as something which is not a
reduction, and not an explanation in the full sense of the word, that
is,
in the sense of a complete reduction of effects to their causes. I
suspect
that, logically speaking, emergent phenomena cannot be explained fully
in as much as the conclusio has to contain more than is given by the
premises,
because the conclusio must designate a new quality. Such deductive
reasoning
is logically impossible.
And
so we have a mix of continuous aspects and discontinuous ones - in the
course of evolution and in the structure of the universe. I don't think
you doubt that the phases of our unfolding cosmos are linked together,
because it is the same cosmos which is unfolding. It is a deep insight
to say that humans are made of the same stuff as, for instance, trees
and
stones. There is continuum between fulgurations. Why should we not be
able
to grasp both the differences and the similarities? Okay, we do this by
communicating. No problem. I would add that it's not a mere
construction;
constructions are made for mapping, they have to prove realistic in
confrontation
with the objects, and they are supposed to help in solving problems
which
arise from social practice. Today, the survival of humanity is at
stake,
and therefore we see the problems of mankind's evolution on the one
hand
as problems which are usually faced by evolutionary systems during
their
process of maturing, and on the other hand as problems which have
specific
features owned only by this specific system, mankind. This is the very
problem, and in trying to find solutions, we recognize the similarities
of all systems in the universe, despite their particularities, and we
are
developing a new information theory which is aware of this.
8. CASTING DIFFERENCES
RC:
Dear
Peter, dear Wolfgang, if we consider the definition of information
proposed
by Lars Qvortrup as "any difference that makes a difference", and
"finding
a difference" (Bateson) , then we could add a new definition by saying
that information consists not only of "making" differences (as in the
case
of nature) or of "finding" differences but also of "designing"
differences.
This last possibiliy can be a most general one, as in the case of
philosophical
ontologies.
My
friend Michael Eldred
uses
the English term "casting" meaning the German "Entwurf" (as in the case
of the Heideggerian "Seinsentwurf"), which is usually translated as
"project".
It is a weaker term that does not give the impression of
anthropocentrism.
In other words, our "castings" are conditioned by an "a-morphical"
dimension
we call matter (and Plato calls chora), as well as by the fact
that
we are facing a non-deterministic universe. Aristotelian physics is a
way
of casting being, as was the Newtonian one, and as is the present
perspective
of looking at things as bytes! This does not mean that there is a
"real"
thing "behind" the phenomena, but that we can cast their being under
different
perspectives. Without doing any kind of casting we see nothing...
the
difference between being and beings is like the one between beings in
their
appeareance under a particular casting, and the given-ness of the
potential
for casting beings in different ways. Corresponding to this
possibility,
i.e. our corresponding to the mere possibility as such, is something
very
related to what Buddhists call nothingness. We always cast in the form
of language, i.e. with other human beings. The casting of being (and of
beings) in the digital form is something we owe to e.g. Quantum Theory,
as well as to Turing (both lines going back to Descartes, Pascal,
Leibniz
etc.) As co-casters we are more a passage than a substance, more an
announcer
(angelos) than a subject.
PF:
Dear Rafael, I certainly agree with you when you bring the perspective
of casting and designing to the concept of information. But a lot of
other
questions arise immediately. Is there any substance which is casted? If
so, on what level of ontology is it located? If not, what are the
conditions
for bringing casting and designing into existence? Is the "passage" of
casting predictable or does it produce something completely new each
time
? In my opinion, the application of your casting theory to real events
in real life has a lot of additional prerequisites. For me, at this
point,
you have to make your understanding of the world clear, otherwise the
concept
of shaping will remain somewhat fuzzy. If we could start with an
evolutionary
concept which does not contradict our findings in science or history, I
think we would be better off, and on a more real pathway of
understanding.
I
cannot subscribe to your general notion of casting as being digital.
Although
it seems to be correct that there is a current technological trend
towards
computerization and networking, contemporary authors exaggerate its
importance.
I, however, prefer a view where digitalization is seen as a particular
kind of shaping or coding of a phenomenon, be it based on matter or
energy.
Although the digital computer is prevailing at this time, and is
dominating
fashionable discourse, other types of coding procedure exist as well
(eg.
analogue and physical).
WH:
Well, let's bring it to a close there. To sum up, Rafael und Peter, I
would
like to ask you to answer one question briefly. You already know how I
feel about this issue; do you think it is possible to conceive and
elaborate
on a unified theory of information?
RC:
Yes, but with the reservation that every viewpoint, be it Newtonian or
digital or whatever, has its own blind spot, which restricts our
vision, and
we have to be aware of this.
PF:
I agree, but don't want to go as far as Rafael when he claims that all
theories are as good as each other. There are differences, and so
some
theories are better than others. Newtonian thinking has been
replaced
by e.g. the superior Theory of Relativity. The former contains
restrictions
which are absent in the latter; thus future theories will uncover
today's
blind spots.
REFERENCES
Last
update: 19 August, 2017